Last November, when I learned that I had cancer, was a
difficult time. But one irony of that period was that just a few days after I
received this diagnosis I was honored with a ceremony celebrating my
appointment as the Martin Professor of Law at New York Law School. The appointment
itself had taken effect on July 1, 2015, but the investiture ceremony was on
November 23, 2015. I was feeling ill, but not so ill as to need to cancel the
ceremony. It was a very special moment for me, and I hope to spend many years
as the Martin Professor.
You can view the event at this URL: http://nyls.mediasite.com/mediasite/Play/bebb8f36b5ca40c091bcbfaca7c3de551d.
And here is a slightly revised text of what I said that night.
The Practice – and
Rule – of Law
Stephen Ellmann
Martin Professor of
Law
New York Law School,
Nov. 23, 2015
Thank you to all of you. This chair
means a lot to me – and your presence even more. Thanks especially to Dean
Crowell, who has supported the development of clinical and experiential
learning so steadfastly – and me too. Thanks also to Jethro Lieberman for his
gracious introduction; I would be proud to hold any chair at New York Law
School, and I’m very glad to hold a chair honoring a man, Lester Martin, who
was so much a part of the life of New York, but I’m honored to succeed two such
scholars as Jethro and Jim Simon in the Martin Chair. Thanks above all to my
family who are here, to Maud, Dave, to Frances, and to Teresa, who makes it
possible for me to do everything.
I want to
say a few more words of thanks to New York Law School. I haven’t been here for
all of New York Law School’s 125 years, but it has been my academic home for 23
years now. I’m grateful for its:
Students
who are so thirsty for understanding and knowledge;
Faculty,
clinicians and classroom teachers alike, who welcomed me to their community and
are my friends, and whose commitment to learning and teaching is evident every
day;
Administration
and staff who go the extra step, or mile, to make the school function
successfully – including, of course, Nancy Guida and her staff, who worked so
hard on this evening – and who even respond to emails sent very late at night
(yes, Susan D’Ambra and Oral Hope, I am talking about you). And with you, I
remember Mary Rose Mercieca, who passed away suddenly last week.
There are
many more people I could thank – please let these brief thank-you’s stand as a
proxy for my gratitude to all of you.
And now
let’s get to work. The issues I’ll discuss this evening are matters many of us
have thought and worried about, but that is okay: my goal, with T.S. Eliot, is
that “we shall not cease from exploration/And the end of all our exploring” –
many lectures and articles and years from now – “will be to arrive where we
started/and know the place for the first time.”
My thesis
this evening can be stated straightforwardly, but I hope will soon grow more
complicated. I mean to argue that the reason why law schools should teach students
how to practice law is not to add to their list of skills but to help prepare
them for the crucial social role they play, namely the preservation and
development of the rule of law.
The “rule
of law” is an elusive though critical idea. I want to say a little about its
components, enough I hope to identify some of its crucial elements though
hardly enough to complete the task of understanding this complex institution. I’ll
define it simply as a system of reasonably predictable laws, enforced through
reasonably just processes, as part of a system that protects human rights. That
definition could be disputed; one might say that the rule of law isn’t directly
connected to the protection of human rights, but South Africa, which spent the
twentieth century demonstrating that societies could be ruled by law without
rights, seems to me to make clear that the rule of law is of necessity
rights-protective, and must be distinguished from what anti-apartheid observers
of South Africa sometimes called “rule by law.”
Lawyers and
judges aren’t the only people responsible for preserving the rule of law, of
course. Police officers are part of the rule of law; so are investment houses’
compliance officers; so are the people who formulate regulations and issue them
for notice-and-comment rulemaking (which I’m discussing with my students in
Legislation and Regulation right now).
But they
are important, in some ways that may seem mundane and others that are more
dramatic. Let me begin a bit indirectly, with uncertainty in the law. In law
school we tend to teach, at least in many of our classes, the tools for
developing and manipulating uncertainty. This statutory text (Leg/Reg again)
might be read according to a canon that says that if Congress left something
out, it intended to do so; or it might be seen as ambiguous enough to be read
in light of some overarching purpose Congress had that might have included the
very word or idea left out of the explicit text. And so on. It’s very hard to
write language that cannot be pushed and pulled by interpretation into meanings
that might surprise its authors. And doing that work must be part of the rule
of law, for reasons I’ll try to explain later.
Meanwhile,
however, a great deal of what lawyers and law users do has very little to do
with such sophisticated ventures into the world of doubt. Much of our legal
world is routinized: driving this fast will get you this kind of a fine;
providing these warranties will satisfy the other side at the closing on your
house; taking this deduction is reasonable while taking that one will look bad
at an audit. All these are individual matters, but I take it the same is true
in much of the legal world of business as well. And even in politics – as
witness the recent resolution of a tied election to the Mississippi legislature
by the faithful application of the prescribed statutory method, drawing straws,
even though the result was that the Democrat was elected and the Republicans
were denied a supermajority in the legislature. There are, in fact, large areas
of reasonably predictable, reasonably stable rules by which people structure
their lives, and lawyers’ role in guiding their clients’ actions in light of
these rules is an integral part of the rule of law. In that sense, and it’s an
important one, every honest lawyer’s work with her clients, on any matter, is
part of sustaining the rule of law. It’s also, of course, part of enabling
clients to exercise autonomy within the law, and morally valuable for that
reason as well. The day-to-day business of law practice is moral work, in somewhat
the same way that the day-to-day practice of medicine is moral work.
A world
governed by the rule of law is not at all a world free of conflict, however,
and another role of lawyers is to help resolve such conflicts. My colleague
Becky Roiphe has explored the twentieth-century professional ideal of legal
professionalism, in which the lawyer is a coordinator of society. In somewhat
the same vein, lawyers are sometimes said to be excellent problem solvers
because they are experts in process. So also Anthony Kronman has written, in
his 1993 book The Lost Lawyer, about
the lawyer-statesman, a lawyer of an earlier age who was distinguished by:
a broad familiarity with diverse and
irreconcilable human goods coupled with an indefatigable willingness to enter
the fray, hear the arguments, render judgment, and articulate the reasons that
support it, even when all hope of moral certainty is gone. At war with itself,
this complex set of attitudes nonetheless describes a recognizable moral ideal,
an ideal closest, perhaps, to the public-spirited stoicism implied the Roman
term gravitas….
I do not at
all want to minimize the importance of this form of professionalism or
statesmanship, but I think we must recognize that it is in a deep sense
conservative. It maintains. It regulates. It does not provide the impetus for
change, at least not so much as it handles change surging from elsewhere.
Justice Harlan, about whom Nadine Strossen spoke so eloquently in her investiture
speech, is perhaps an exemplar of this wise conservatism. It’s to be admired,
but it isn’t the whole of lawyers’ role in change.
The impetus for change remains to
be accounted for. I’ve learned about the importance of change in the rule of
law from several sources. Ed Purcell’s history, in particular his book on “Brandeis
and the Progressive Constitution,” convinced me that the rule of law rests on no
absolute foundations at all. There are vast areas of relative stability, but
nothing lasts forever, neither the texts nor the meanings of texts, and in fact
lawyers’ (and judges’) reasoning and advocacy skills are always being deployed
in efforts to change the rules in one direction or another. Often, moreover,
these efforts are not purely motivated, and not transparently conducted. This
too is part of the actual nature of the rule of law. Similarly Frank Munger, in
his ongoing work on Thailand’s cause lawyers, seems to me to be demonstrating
that the path to the rule of law doth not run straight, both because the moves
that may make a positive difference in any society depend on the nature of that
society, and because the ultimate outcome – that society’s rule of law – may
turn out to be quite different from ours.
Struggle is
integral to the rule of law, and by no means all of it is modulated by the
august lawyer-statesmen of Kronman’s vision. For me, that lesson came through
most clearly in South Africa, which has been an important part of my academic
work and my life since the mid-1980s. The critical lesson South Africa teaches
on this score is that many of the greatest lawyer-statesmen – in South Africa,
all of us know of Nelson Mandela, but Arthur Chaskalson, my friend and the
first head of South Africa’s new post-apartheid Constitutional Court, stands
out as well – were not dispassionate. They had not lost all hope of moral
certainty. They were deft, even masterful, in their use of the tools of legal
argument available to them, but they were never infatuated by those tools.
Instead, they were absolutely certain of the rightness of their cause, the
fight against the inhuman blight of apartheid. Mahatma Gandhi, another lawyer,
was no less convinced of the rightness of overthrowing British colonialism.
When we stop to think about our own history, moreover, we see many similar
examples: Thomas Jefferson, John Adams, Abraham Lincoln, Franklin Delano
Roosevelt, Thurgood Marshall, Ruth Bader Ginsburg. These statesmen and stateswomen
were not stoics but revolutionaries, either metaphorically or literally. Some,
like their counterparts in South Africa, violated the law, sometimes
extensively, in what I would call the cause of the rule of law. And this too is
a role that the lawyers we are educating may come to take up.
So now we
come to the question of how clinical and experiential education contribute to
students’ ability to play this range of roles in the ongoing creation of the
rule of law. I want to begin in a sense paradoxically, with the impact of this
kind of education on legal reasoning – paradoxically because legal reasoning is
often thought to be the domain and the subject of classroom courses; then ask
which clinics can best have this and related impacts for which students; and
then look at two overarching contributions to the rule of law that legal
education in the practice of law has provided: the liberatory effect of the
idea of client-centeredness, and the profound clarification that this form of
education offers into the moral nature, and moral ambiguity, of lawyers’
contribution to the making of the rule of law.
Let me
start with legal reasoning, acknowledged by all as absolutely integral to the
lawyer’s work. I don’t at all suggest that clinical and experiential education
is a substitute for classroom training in legal reasoning; but equally
classroom training is often not a substitute for clinical and experiential
education, even with respect to legal reasoning. After all, expertise theory
indicates that expertise consists of mastery of a domain. Transferable
expertise is limited, if it exists at all: an expert musician is not an expert
conductor, an expert in moral philosophy is not an expert in literature. And an
expert in legal reasoning from books is not an expert in legal reasoning that
must begin from an encounter with a client, and the client’s ambiguous facts
and ambivalent desires, and work from there towards a legal approach that will
achieve the client’s objectives. If we trained our students – we don’t do this
at New York Law School – but if we trained our students only to be expert
reasoners from books, we would have trained them in the wrong thing.
But to
speak of legal reasoning by itself implies that this skill is something
disembodied, distinct from the rest of the makeup of the individuals who employ
it. If emotion shapes cognition, as much
current research tells us, then emotion surely shapes learning as well. Few
things give students so much reason to learn as the awareness that a client’s
wellbeing turns on what the student, acting as a lawyer, does. And few things
give students so much of a sense of accomplishment as having in fact
successfully protected a client’s interest. If we cannot give students these
powerful experiences, we risk dampening their curiosity and limiting their
engagement. We risk undercutting their learning not just of the values of
client representation, but of the elements of legal reasoning.
All this is
quite general; let me now be more concrete about which clinics can have this
impact for which students. Data collected in two NALP surveys, and soon to be
discussed in a forthcoming Clinical Law
Review article by Meg Reuter and Joanne Ingham, make clear that students
who choose public interest law find a home in skills courses and especially in
those where they work on actual legal matters, clinics and externships. Many of
these students, I’m sure, are also thrilled by the chance to work with
like-minded faculty; their clinic and externship experiences give them the
chance to live, and develop, their ideals; and their experiences also help them
to enter the job market with credentials and references that may make a crucial
difference. I think we do a very good job launching these students into the
world – and these are, I suspect, the students likeliest to play the rule of
law role of demanding that the system change.
But what
about the students who graduate and enter private practice? The NALP data,
admittedly focused in this respect on students who enter big-firm private
practice and so not necessarily applicable to students who go into other forms
of private law, say that these future private practitioners took fewer clinical
and experiential courses while they were in law school, and – though those who
took the courses liked them – they liked them less than their future public-interest
counterparts did.
What
accounts for this? It seems to me that one likely answer is that the future
private practitioners doubted that taking courses focused on public interest or
public service practice – as most clinics and most externships probably are –
would really help them prepare for the careers they envisioned. That surely
reduced their motivation. Moreover, they were probably right. Again, expertise
theory says that we become expert in domains. While the exact dimensions of a
domain can be debated (as Ian Weinstein has reminded me), criminal defense is a
long ways from patent law. It is easier to take what we learn in one area and
apply it to another that is very similar than it is to transfer it to some
field dramatically removed from the one in which we have been trained.
I think it
follows from this that we clearly need clinical and experiential training that
is set in or near the fields of private practice into which our students are
likely to move. In fact, at NYLS we already have several such clinics, and are
discussing more. Needless to say, I also think our traditional, social-justice
minded, clinical and experiential offerings are essential. Happily, at NYLS,
with the benefit of the wonderful gift from Joseph Plumeri that has given us
the Plumeri Center for Social Justice and Economic Opportunity – thank you,
Dean Crowell, for securing this gift for us – we have the opportunity to build
on multiple fronts. But what I most want to say is that, if I am right that the
roles our students will play in the private practice of law will be part of the
maintenance of the rule of law – a rule of law that aims for justice and honors
human rights – then creating such clinics is not a departure from a social
justice mission. Instead it is another way to contribute to social justice. And
it is actually a very special opportunity: to infuse into the teaching of the
practice of law in these fields a sense of their social significance, so that
we do not wind up essentially telling our graduates that their work is only
socially meaningful if it falls in the cabin of what we call public interest
law.
Now I’d
like to talk about two broader ways in which what clinical and experiential
courses teach about the practice of law is specially important to students’ and
graduates’ contribution to the rule of law. The first is the idea of
client-centeredness, probably the single most important element of the past 40
years’ academic, that is to say clinical, reconceptualization of law practice.
Clinicians study law practice as doctrinal teachers study law doctrine, and the
impact of that somewhat removed reflection is important. The idea of client-centeredness
can be seen, as Becky Roiphe has thoughtfully argued, as a form of lawyers’
drawing back from their professional role of managing social conflict. That
point has force, especially if client-centeredness is understood as a form of
self-enforced passivity on the part of the lawyer in his or her interactions
with the client. But I don’t see it that way; I think client-centeredness is or
should be, in a phrase Bob Dinerstein coined, engaged client-centeredness, in
which the lawyer offers the client the full benefit of the lawyer’s experience
while trying hard to simultaneously assist the client to make his or her own
choices. In calling on lawyers to practice this way, and training their
students to go out into the world to practice this way, clinicians have been
adding to the foundation of the rule of law, by removing a form of lawless or
arbitrary power – the lawyer’s imposition of his or her will – from the
processes of the law itself. And the work is not done: the lawyer-client
relationship is, in many ways, an unequal one, and developing an understanding
of what the lawyer committed to the rule of law should offer her client is a
task that is not yet complete.
The last
contribution to educating our students for the rule of law that I’ll discuss is
surely the most paradoxical. We teach them about moral values. Often we do so
by supporting the students’ most idealistic impulses, which contribute so much
to achieving zealous and caring representation. But we also do so in good part
by teaching them about moral ambiguity. Lawyers are faithful to legal texts –
except that what those texts mean is always subject to argument and reargument,
and almost no one seems to think, really, that the answer to the question of
what does a text mean is “what did its author intend?” Or to give a different,
and important, example: Richard Sherwin has been exploring in depth the ways
that today’s media, such as film and video, affect how legal decisions are
made. But once we know that these effects exist, we know that lawyers will –
indeed, as zealous advocates, must – make use of them. As Richard has argued,
in principle this is no different than what advocates since Demosthenes have
done with the techniques of rhetoric.
And the point can be generalized:
as we learn about human beings’ cognitive limitations, we also, at the very
same time, are learning about techniques that might manipulate those cognitive
limitations. So in recent years there has been a lot of attention to the power
of narrative as a way to convey to a decisionmaker the human essence of a
situation. But we know that human beings’ reasoning is limited by what’s called
the “heuristic of availability,” which essentially says that people tend to
decide things based on the examples of such things that come most readily to
mind. The risk of shark bites is exaggerated because the stories stick in our
minds; and narrative helps make things stick in our minds. So of course we
should use narrative, but we should be clear about the extent to which we are
engaged not in presenting “truth” but in conveying, within the rules to be
sure, a story of what the truth might be. And as students learn these skills,
they also encounter, often and perhaps inevitably, the reality that their
clients – on whose behalf they engage in such careful presentation, and for
whose wellbeing they care so much – may be lying.
And this brings us back,
emphatically, to the rule of law. Ed Purcell has wonderfully examined the
maneuvers of judges, in particular, as they seek to shape and reshape the legal
system. But maneuver, manipulation, is part of the rule of law at every stage.
I don’t mean to suggest that this behavior is lawless or unprincipled. Quite
the opposite: it is law-governed and should be principled, and this behavior is
an integral part of our creation of a rule of law. From the crooked timber of
humanity nothing completely straight can be made; but from the lawyer’s role in
seeking, for flawed people and by means that may exploit other people’s
limitations, what the law provides, from that role can and does come a rule of
law. We can arrive at this place, and because we and our students know it for
the first time, make of it the best place that it can be.