I found myself thinking the other day about how important
the framing of the question is to the answers you’ll get – even in such a
subtle area as the understanding of people’s moral thinking.
Here’s a famous moral question, framed to help gauge the
answerer’s level of moral development: the Heinz dilemma posed by Lawrence
Kohlberg. As quoted in Wikipedia from Kohlberg’s Essays in Moral Development, Vol. 1 (1981), it reads:
Heinz's
wife was near death, and her only hope was a drug that had been discovered by a
pharmacist who was selling it for an exorbitant price. The drug cost $20,000 to
make, and the pharmacist was selling it for $200,000. Heinz could only raise
$50,000 and insurance wouldn't make up the difference. He offered what he had
to the pharmacist, and when his offer was rejected, Heinz said he would pay the
rest later. Still the pharmacist refused. In desperation, Heinz considered
stealing the drug. Would it be wrong for him to do that?
Should Heinz have
broken into the store to steal the drug for his wife? Why or why not?
Carol Gilligan, in her book In A Different Voice: Psychological
Theory and Women’s Development
(1993), famously contrasted 11-year-old Jake’s perception of this problem
as “‘sort of like a math problem with humans,’” to be resolved using an ethic
of rights, and 11-year-old Amy’s contrasting response of framing the issue as
arising in “a narrative of relationships that extends over time,” to be
addressed using an ethic of care. The two responses are strikingly different ,
though whether that difference reflects a gender difference in ethical thinking
is another, and complex, question. What’s striking to me now is a point that
Gilligan may also recognize, but as far as I now recall does not make central:
that the presentation of the problem itself potentially shapes the answers it
elicits.
To put the
matter more directly, Kohlberg’s question is precisely designed to pose an
ethics question that is like a math problem. It’s meant, as many a law
professor’s Socratic question is, to exclude all possible issues except one: in
this case, the sheer conflict between two claims of moral right (respect for
property and respect for life).
Those questions have their uses, in
particular for encouraging students to practice skills of precision in
identifying issues and reasoning about them. The price of asking such questions,
however, is that if they work they narrow discussion and thought down to
whatever line of reasoning the professor wants to focus on. They may also implicitly
devalue, and they certainly aim to disregard at least for the moment, the many
other thoughts and concerns that students may want to bring to bear on the
matter at hand.
Perhaps these questions also
reflect something true about the world – that sometimes stark choices must be
made. But this claim is debatable. It’s been debated, in fact, in connection
with the “ticking bomb” scenarios often advanced as the basis for moral
argument about torture. If the ticking bomb scenario appeared in the actual
world, its resolution might be a matter of constructing the right hierarchy of
rights, the right of the terrorist not to be tortured and the right of his
imminent victims not to be killed. But in the real world, there may never be a
question so stark as the ticking bomb scenario’s assumed facts – which imagine
that we know exactly who might have to be tortured, under circumstances so
urgent as to admit of no alternative except immediate action. As some very thoughtful
observers have argued, if the real world is messier than the scenario, then thinking
about the ticking bomb scenario may be a beguiling distraction.
But whatever the virtues and
defects of these questions, for pedagogical or truth-seeking purposes, their
power as questions is important to recognize. If we ask an 11-year-old, or a
45-year-old, a math problem about morality, it seems reasonable for us to
predict that he, or she, will respond with a math answer about morality. Does
that mean that the person answering actually views morality as a math problem?
Perhaps – that would be one reason to respond this way. But perhaps not. Maybe
he, or she, understands the question as ruling out any choices except (to use
the Heinz dilemma in particular) to steal or not to steal. The question as
phrased doesn’t quite do that, and it might take a much longer problem to
explicitly exclude all other options. Still, the problem does seem meant to be
understood this way. Maybe the person answering the question views questioners
as entitled to answers that address the sort of question they meant to ask.
Maybe he, or she, also assumes that math problems are problems to be responded
to with math answers.
One might say a lot about the
psychological traits these inclinations reflect – a conformance with authority,
possibly, or maybe a generous desire to help the questioner. But whatever one
might say on those scores, and whatever those observations might have to do
with gender, they wouldn’t necessarily have much to do with whether the person
being questioned thought about morality in terms of rights or relationships.
Here as elsewhere it’s very
important to ask the right question. Otherwise the chance you’ll get the wrong
answer has to increase.
No comments:
Post a Comment