The opinion in Glossip v. Gross by
Justice Breyer, joined by Justice Ginsburg, lays out their reasons for
believing that the Supreme Court should address head-on the issue of whether
the death penalty is constitutional in any circumstances. To my mind, the case the
opinion makes is cogent. I think Breyer and Ginsburg are right to say, in particular, that a
penalty applied so inconsistently, both failing to systematically punish
"the worst of the worst" and on occasion likely falling on people who
are actually innocent, can't be justified, especially outside the context of
war. (War may be different, essentially because life is so often taken in war
anyway. But the Guantanamo war crimes investigations and prosecutions have been so emphatically problematic that I am inclined to say that here too the arguments against the
death penalty are persuasive.)
The
impossibility of running a death penalty system fairly, reliably and
consistently means that the death penalty should be unconstitutional. But it
doesn't quite mean that it is unconstitutional.
Justice Scalia
responds to Breyer's argument with this observation (among others): "It is
impossible to hold unconstitutional that which the Constitution explicitly contemplates." (Scalia, J.,
concurring, at 2.) (Emphasis in original.) There's no disputing that both the
Fifth and Fourteenth Amendment do "contemplate" capital punishment.
The Fifth Amendment addresses the requirements for trial of a "capital ...
crime," and both Amendments forbid the government from depriving
anyone of "life" without due process of law.
But while the
Constitution certainly “contemplates” the existence of capital punishment, no
one claims that it mandates that capital punishment be one of the penalties
American jurisdictions employ. Clearly, also, some things the Constitution did
not contemplate have come to be part of our world. The Framers in 1787 did not
contemplate an Air Force. Nor, I’ve read, did they contemplate (that is, expect
the rise of) political parties.
Here’s one
more example: The Framers did not anticipate the development of an economy that
was so massively interconnected that the power to regulate interstate commerce,
which they explicitly granted to Congress in the Constitution, could come to
encompass the regulation of almost anything. Whatever the exact limits on a
proper modern interpretation of the reach of the interstate commerce clause (a
question still, and perhaps forever, under debate), the changes of the past two
centuries – only dimly foreseen, if at all, by the framers, have added to
congressional power and reduced state authority.
That last
point is of particular importance here, because what has happened is not only
that federal power has grown but that state power has contracted. That’s
striking, because the Tenth Amendment of the Constitution can be said to “explicitly
require,” not just “contemplate,” the preservation of state power. The Tenth Amendment provides that: “The
powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited
by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the
people.” This language, although its exact meaning becomes elusive as soon as
it is carefully parsed, nevertheless plainly is asserting not only what the
Framers “contemplated” but what they meant to mandate. Yet the authority of the
states has in fact been reduced by the uncontemplated impact of social change,
as transmuted into constitutional understanding. Clearly we can only see this evolution as constitutionally acceptable if we believe that the meaning of the constitution’s words can evolve
over time – but I do believe that, and in fact believe that a constitution as
hard to amend as ours can only remain meaningful over centuries of time if its words’
meaning can evolve with the circumstances they govern.
So I don’t
think that what the Framers “explicitly contemplated” is necessarily
constitutional today. Justice Breyer writes, and I agree, that “‘the
Constitution contemplates that in the
end our own judgment will be brought to bear on the question of the
acceptability of the death penalty under the Eighth Amendment.’” (Breyer, J.,
dissenting, at 40.) (Emphasis added.)
But what
Breyer says doesn’t directly address the question of how to read the
Constitution if it “contemplates” two opposing things – in this case, the
potential unconstitutionality and the assumed constitutionality of capital
punishment. I want to turn to this question of what to make of a possible
self-contradictory constitution in a coming post.
No comments:
Post a Comment